Ultimate Reality
BY THE REV.
LEWIS F. HITE, M.A.,
Professor
of Philosophy, New Church Theological School,
Cambridge, MA
International Swedenborg Congress,
London, July 4 to 8, 1910
ULTIMATE REALITY is the
proper designation of the subject about which philosophy is peculiarly
concerned.
In assigning me this
subject, therefore, the Congress is asking that I present my views on
the central theme of philosophy, and yet I am not sure that this
effort would be the natural response to the present occasion.
I presume there is on
the part of this assembly a general agreement as to what ultimate
reality is; and accordingly I am expected to make some comments on
what we all have more or less definitely in mind. In other words, I
take it for granted that among students of Swedenborg these is
complete agreement as to the doctrine that God is the only really
existing and self-subsisting being in the universe. So, then, we may
say at once, God is the ultimate reality, and our thoughts thus pass
from the realm of philosophy to that of theology.
But I do not interpret
my task as identical with that of dogmatic or even systematic
theology, and I am sure you would all be disappointed if I should
content myself with merely reciting Swedenborg's familiar doctrines
about the nature of God and the world.
Indeed, the mere recital
of these doctrines would raise questions of interpretation of the most
profound and far-reaching kind. If, for instance, we should say God is
love and wisdom, and add that love and wisdom are the very and only
substance and form, we make an assertion that goes to the very bottom
of metaphysics. If, now, we note that the point of this doctrine is
philosophically that substance and form are love and wisdom rather
than that love and wisdom are substance and form, we see that it
presents a new view of substance and form. So, too, if we affirm that
God is love we merely repeat Christian tradition, but if we assert
that love is God we announce the fundamental thesis of a new
revelation—a thesis which gives new significance to the word love, and
transforms the theological doctrine that God is the Ultimate Reality
to the philosophical statement the ultimate reality is love. It seems
inevitable, then, that I must, with what light I have from our
doctrines and from history in general, undertake to say what Ultimate
Reality is as I conceive it. First, then, let us glance at history.
From the days of the
early Greeks, all down through the ages to the present time, the
intellectual energies of the master minds of our race have been
directed to the underlying problems of existence and of life. The
human mind is so constituted that the facts of ordinary experience
inevitably suggest deeper meanings; but the practical exigencies of
daily life also demand a knowledge of the relations and connections of
things sufficient to ensure the success of foresight, purpose and
method. In this way the intellectual and the practical needs of
mankind have combined in infinitely various fashion to bring order and
system into the field of raw experience. Success and failure, trial
and error, furnish the workshop for sharpening wits and acquiring
skill. The fit and the unfit, the deceptive and the certain, the
changing and the permanent, the varying and the constant, the apparent
and the known, tend to fall into familiar and convenient groups which
henceforth serve the purposes of both practical and intellectual
control and progress. Under these circumstances, as the inevitable
outcome of practical and rational intelligence, the distinction
between appearance and reality was established, and the notion of
ultimate reality gradually came to be defined. Ordinary practical life
is satisfied with relative stability and permanence in the objects
with which it has to do. The timber and stones, the bricks and mortar,
the iron and steel with which we build our houses, keep their shape
and stay where they are put sufficiently to ensure the correctness of
calculations made generations and centuries ahead. On the other hand,
trees and plants, and especially animals, exhibit changes of growth,
decay and movement such that no certain prediction about their future
condition at any given time is possible. To-day the grass is in the
field, tomorrow it is cast into the oven. The very predicate of
existence, when we press it too bard, becomes ambiguous and uncertain.
We cannot say is and keep to it. The "is" passes inevitably and almost
instantaneously into “was." The predicate of existence, under such
stress and strain, becomes infected with change and variety, so that
it seems, superficially at any rate, impossible to assert existence
without qualification in any case whatsoever. The granite rocks and
the everlasting hills appear to the eye of the geologist as momentary
aspects of all-pervading change. Πάvτα χωρεi κai οiδέν μένει, as the
wise men of old said. All things are in a flux; nothing is. Thus we
see that the practical stability of things becomes, on further
acquaintance, merely relative. But even relative stability suggests
degrees, while practical convenience forces the task of distinguishing
the more from the less stable, thus setting up a serial arrangement
which would, upon the supervening of intellectual motives, be carried
back to the least and forward to the greatest degree of stability.
Such a scheme of things occasions the rational demand for absolute
stability on the one hand, and the entire lack of stability on the
other. These demands are satisfied by that which is changeless from
any and every point of view, and that which is ever changing. The
motives herein concerned are genuine and constant human motives, ever
operative and ever effective. They lead in one direction to the
conception of the real as that which is absolutely abiding, superior
to all change and yet the ground of all change. In the other direction
they lead to the conception of a universal, ceaseless flux.
These motives were
conspicuously present in early Greek philosophy. The world of humanity
was already very very old when the Greek race first appeared upon the
stage of history. General views of the world and of life had become
common property, so as to be motives and subjects for literary
treatment. Intellectual interests had begun to stir the minds of men
with larger and deeper questions than those which the needs of
ordinary practical life made urgent. This was the situation when Early
Greek philosophy entered upon its unique and brilliant career. In the
older mythologies and cosmogonies, the world of phenomena had been
reduced to order and system. Ονμανόs, Γαία, 'Ωκεανόs, and the eldest
of the gods, 'Epos, appear as representing the beginning.
Thence follows the generation and order of things down to the present
world of ordinary observation. Here that which is original, the
beginner and the begetter, appears as the ultimate reality. The
prime source of things and the powers of begetting, or production, are
looked to for explanation of the actual world, arid in mythological
language a complete explanation was given. But such explanations did
not go very far in accounting for the actual present behaviour of
things. Attention was accordingly more and more directed to the
existing order, and interest was transferred from questions of origin
to questions as to the present. The question, What the world was at
the beginning? was changed to, What the world is now? as it stands.
When, therefore, Thales, 600 years B.C., declared that all things came
from water, he gave expression to a new view of the world. For when
Anaximines said the world was mist, when Anaximander said it was the
boundless, when Heraclitus said it was fire, and Empedocles that it
was earth, air, fire and water, and Anaxagoras that it was a mixture
of an infinite number of infinitely small elements or seeds, they all
gave substantially the same answer, namely, that the world is a single
homogeneous body, or a mixture of such bodies, and all things are made
out of this body or mixture. Reflection upon these various answers,
and criticism of there, led to the recognition of other general
features of the world besides background and things. Heraclitus
directed attention to all-pervading change. For him the world is a
process, and fire is the body which constitutes this
process. Fire is the reality; the things which we observe are mere
stages and appearances which this ever-living fire undergoes and
presents. The philosophy of Heraclitus makes the fact of change
central, fundamental and real. Parmenides, on the other hand, directed
attention to the fact of permanence. To ordinary observation, things
abide and also change. But, said Heraclitus, look a little closer and
you will see that everything changes. Nothing really remains the same
from moment to moment. In the upward movement of the flame and the
unceasing motion of the flowing river, we have the true types of the
real nature of things.
Parmenides, however,
insisted that if you look still closer you will see that change is
mere appearance and presupposes the permanent. A thing must persist
through its changes if it is to exhibit change at all. That which
persists in and through change is the real in things. The real world,
then, is a changeless, homogeneous, continuous body.
These two views of the
world recognize and emphasize two fundamental characters of
experience, and they have maintained themselves in all subsequent
metaphysics. The effort to reconcile them forced early Greek
philosophy to its final position. It was seen that the real world must
be in some sense abiding; it was also seen that variety and change
must in some way belong to it. The issue between permanence and
change, oneness and variety, was definitely sharpened by the conflict
between the uncompromising monism of Parmenides and the thoroughgoing
Pythagorean pluralism. According to the latter doctrine, the world is
number, and things are made out of numbers, not, of course, abstract,
but concrete numbers. But, if things are made up of a number of parts,
then the parts themselves would be made up of still smaller parts, and
so on ad infinitum. In other words, anything, however small,
would be made up of an infinite number of parts, and it would follow
that if these parts have any magnitude whatsoever the thing would be
infinitely large, if no magnitude the thing would be nothing. So that
everything would be at once so small as to be nothing at all, and so
large as to be infinitely large. It was these consequences which the
famous undying paradoxes of Zeno brought out with inexorable logic and
precision. From Zeno's criticism it was seen to be practically
necessary to put a stop to division, and to assume real bodies so
small as to be no longer capable of natural division. It was in this
way that early Greek thought reached the atomic theory. Taken
separately, these invisible and indivisible bodies had all the
properties of the Parmenidean one, and could be real in the
Parmenidean sense; taken together, they provided for change and
variety by their movements and combinations. This theory forces
Heraclitus, Pythagoras, and Parmenides to terms and in a way satisfies
their demands. The world, for this theory, consists of atoms, motion
and void. Solid bodies moving in empty space, give us, by their
combinations, the many and various things of the actual world. The
real world, then, is matter in motion. This is the answer which
early Greek philosophy gave, and for scientific purposes it is the
most definite and satisfactory answer that has ever been given. We are
left in the dark as to the fate of the atomic theory during the
transition period from early Greek philosophy to that of Plato and
Aristotle, but the penetrating analysis of sense perception, summed up
in the dictum of Protagoras, "Man is the measure of all things," laid
the basis for a new departure, and gave rise to the problem of
knowledge which has held the centre of the stage in philosophy ever
since. Protagoras left philosophy with the simple question, If in
sense perception we know directly only our sensations, has knowledge a
real object, and what is that object? This question cannot be answered
in terms of the atomic theory, for the atom is clearly but a minimized
object of sense perception, and so is, strictly speaking, a sensation,
no more real than any other sensation. Like other sensations, its
existence depends on the state of the perceiver, and therefore it has
no independent reality. This seems to be the course of thought which
led the classic age of Greek philosophy to the prompt and final
rejection of the atomic theory and to the search for reality in
another direction. Socrates emphasized the practical certainty of
knowledge as presupposed in conduct. Man is characteristically and
essentially a moral being, whose real nature consists in expressing
purposes. But a purpose is, from one point of view, an ideal, or a
concept. The business of the moral life, therefore, is to form clear
concepts and express them in conduct. Plato lifted such concepts into
a purely abstract realm and gave them an independent existence. The
doctrine of ideas was thus substituted in philosophy for the atomic
theory. The real world is now the world of independent ideas,
rather than independent atoms. The world as it is for thought takes
the place of the world as it is for sense. In this way the search for
the abiding, for that which is ever one and the same, was ended, since
it is the very nature of a concept to be unalterable,
to persist in all its
applications, and to furnish the eternal standard by which all
expressions and embodiments of it are to be tested. It is the eternal
truth. The logical and epistemological grounds of this doctrine are so
firm, and so deeply embedded in human experience, that it has occupied
the field of philosophy ever since as the only successful rival of
materialism, and as the mainstay and justification of all the highest
aspirations and strivings of men. Thereafter, the ultimate reality was
sought not in the sensuous world, as bad been the case in early Greek
philosophy, but in the super-sensuous. The things of the spirit of man
were placed above the things of the body. Spirit, not matter, was the
eternal substance of things. This has been the contention of all
idealistic philosophies down to the present day.
Aristotle did little to
modify this doctrine, but he did much to work out its consequences in
detail. It is far from my intention to attempt any critical summary of
Aristotelian philosophy. This philosophy was in some respects the
unique intellectual achievement of the race, and was the culmination
of what was, perhaps, the race's supreme intellectual effort. Never
was the human intellect so stirred as during the period spanned by the
lives of Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. A page of Aristotle's
metaphysics taken at random gives a bewildering impression of the
almost desperate intellectual struggle of the Greek mind of his day.
Aristotle's achievement was the complete organization of human science
on the basis of a marvelously simplified conceptual apparatus. The
scheme of things which he constructed on this basis was transmitted to
posterity, and has become the web and tissue of our common knowledge,
so that Aristotelianism is but another name for our modern
common-sense. If, however, we look closely at the metaphysical
character of Aristotelianism, we shall see that the system is
determined by two fundamental influences: the habits of language and
the requirements of abstract thought. We have already seen hew the
practical needs of mankind led to the analysis and reconstruction of
experience, and how early Greek philosophy followed out these motives
in the construction of the atomic theory. Aristotle, on the basis of
results so reached, immensely extended and systematized the field of
inquiry, and carried forward analysis and reconstruction under the
stimulus of motives more purely intellectual. We know from “the
Metaphysics" that Aristotle read early Greek philosophy as a more or
less blind attempt to work out the notion of cause, and he saw in it a
greater or less approximation to his own doctrine of the four
conceptions of cause. It appeared to him naturally that early Greek
philosophy was concerned especially with the material cause. Whereas
if we take his system as a whole, it is evident that he placed the
emphasis on the efficient cause, and his philosophy took the form of a
system of development. But the notion of development itself
presupposes that of formal cause and also that of final cause. The
finch cause in turn presupposed a universe complete and perfect in
idea, in whole and in part, and the formal cause, as original essence,
by its own development realized this ideal. To Aristotle, the
Heraclitean flux was the process in which and by which essence
developed its specific quality and its own proper form. The form, as
end or terminus of movement, was also object of striving, and as such
already present in its completeness as idea. It is obvious that we
have here a carefully thought out attempt to give in biological terms
a specific meaning to Plato's notions of expression and participation
of the idea. In this view, the universe already and eternally exists,
spread out to view, one and complete. Movement and change, birth,
growth, decay and death, are merely transitions from point to point
within this static whole. The world of variety and qualities thus
dissolves into the changeless body of the Parmenidean one, and
we need to take only one step more to enter the mechanical world of
pure mathematics. This outcome was made inevitable by the
presuppositions of early Greek philosophy which Aristotle, on the
basis of language and common-sense, appropriated without criticism.
Early Greek philosophy, as we saw, began with the idea of a common
background to the body of phenomena, and the term used to designate it
was φύσιs (nature). This notion of φύσιs as the material background of
all the phenomena of the actual world was a permanent and, it would
seem, an ineradicable achievement of human thought. It is the ultimate
basis of all forms of materialism, and has its origin in the peculiar
function of the intellect itself. It may take the form of Democritean
atoms, or the centres of force of Boscovich, or a homogeneous ethereal
medium. In all these forms it is the outcome of analysis which has its
beginning in the ordinary operations of the intellect in practical
life. Practical life demands stable objects, objects that remain
self-identical, unchanged throughout any given operation, and achieves
success by selecting or constructing such objects. All our
intellectual operations primarily serve our practical life by
discovering or by establishing order among such objects. The essence
of this intellectual activity consists in detaching from the concrete
life the character of permanence. In the course of time, this element
of permanence is universalized and made the presupposition of all
thought and the basis of all life. Thus universalized, it is what the
Greeks called φύσιs, and what we call nature.
But the process of
analysis and abstraction does not stop here. The element of permanence
is individualized and located in a system of conceptual objects,
giving rise to what we call the world of concepts, in Platonic
language the world of ideas. The further the process of abstraction is
carried, and the more the concepts are simplified, the nearer the
approach to a mere system of relations in the homogeneous field of
empty space. In other words, we are led by this process to a world
which takes on more and more the character of a rigid mechanical
system. This is precisely the result achieved by the human intellect
in the development of Greek philosophy from Thales to Aristotle.
Aristotle's god was the apotheosis of the element of permanence, the
unchanged and the unmoved cause of the world. His universe was a
static whole, already complete, in which succession and quality were
reducible ultimately to bare moments, and time itself was only a
one-dimensional and reversible way of taking points in the spread-out
field of space. Any critical estimate of Aristotle's philosophy must
do justice to the various and complicated human motives which
everywhere pervade it, but we must look for the key in the aims and
methods of his analysis. A pupil of Plato for twenty years, and, as a
consequence, a master of dialectic and of historical movements, his
gigantic intellect swept the field of nature and of experience with
penetrating insight and marvelous comprehensiveness. He gathered up,
sifted, and recast the results of human thinking even though already
presented by the consummate genius of Plato. The outcome was
determined by one single controlling conception, the conception of
subject. This conception leads back to the φύσιs of early Greek
philosophy, and now appears under the twofold aspect of material cause
and of essence; the universal underlying background of phenomena;
νποκείμενου; the substantia of the Latin; what we English know
as substance, the bearer of qualities, activities, changes; in short,
the subject of predicates. Whatever may be the metaphysical value of
that which we call substance or thing, we are indebted to Aristotle
for the clear and definite conception of it, and we do not have to
look far for his motives and methods of procedure. We have seen that
the world of practical life, with its concrete objects in all their
variety and changes, falls a victim to the processes of analysis and
abstraction which are demanded as the necessary conditions of
practical success. Stability, plasticity, movability, divisibility,
self-identity, independence, are the properties which practical
success demands and utilizes, and these are precisely the characters
which the intellect discovers, abstracts and transforms into a
conceptual world. No doubt thee processes would go on under any
conditions where the will and intellect could co-operate, but the
supreme agency for promoting the accumulation, preservation and
organization of such experience is the faculty of speech and the use
of language. But the development of language itself is due to the
intellectual functions of attention, discrimination, selection—in a
word, analysis and abstraction. Language is a very simple but
effective means of preserving the results of these processes. When a
character is once noticed and a name is given it, the name then serves
to recall it and so preserve it. Language thus serves practical
convenience and acquires practical importance. It is a shorthand
method of reproducing and forecasting experience. But it is equally
serviceable for intellectual purposes, both as a register and a
shorthand method of thought. This dependence of intellect upon speech
gradually develops a habit which is further cultivated by reading and
writing. So that ordinary thought is in such wise symbolic that mere
words are used in the place of conceptions, and systems of
word-building become themselves objects of construction and
reflection. The result is, we have in due course the science of
grammar and that marvelous creation about which the science of grammar
revolves-the sentence. The sentence is the unique embodiment of
conceptual thought. The subject represents the oneness and
changelessness of the concept, and the predicate represents the
various qualities and relations of the concept. The two simple
elements of the sentence thus acquire metaphysical and logical value.
Thought proceeds, as we have seen, by severing an observed character
from the concrete experience in which it is found. This tree is green,
that tree is green, and so on indefinitely. Here "tree" stands for the
abiding background, and "green" for the constant character. We have
various terms for designating this distinction. In grammar it is
substantive and adjective; in metaphysics it is thing and quality,
substance and form, or substance and attribute; in logic, subject and
predicate, term and relation, subject and object. Now, observe that
both subject and predicate are concepts, and the concepts are united
by a third concept which we call a relation. The two concepts in this
relation become subject and predicate, and constitute what we call a
judgment. The judgment, expressed in words, is the sentence.
This analysis was
required to emphasize the fact that thought proceeds with concepts,
and language is the product of thought; but thought itself has
developed historically as the servant of practical life, and has been
controlled by this use. Nevertheless, after having reached a certain
stage of development, thought became itself the object of independent
interest, and it may be said that Greek philosophy culminates in the
triumph of this interest. In other words, Aristotle's logic was the
characteristic achievement of Greek philosophy.
In the light of the
foregoing discussion we are now able to see that the inevitable
outcome of Aristotle's philosophy was empty formalism, a reduction of
all concrete experience to abstract conceptions. His analysis of
experience stopped with the identification of concepts, and his logic
was a formal treatment of concepts in abstracto. It inhered in
his undertaking that the further he went in the investigation and
treatment of formal thought, the further he left behind him both the
concrete experience and the practical life from which he set out. This
criticism, however, does not in the least depreciate the value of his
achievement. It merely calls attention to its proper character and
function in the development of philosophy. Nor does it ignore the fact
that Aristotle's conception of reality was far richer than that which
the logical outcome of his method indicated. We need to be reminded
that Aristotle was not fully conscious of his task as metaphysician.
He accepted in the main the results of Early Greek philosophy. He
adopted without thorough going criticism the presuppositions of
ordinary thought and common-sense. He saw in language the natural,
characteristic, arid fundamental expression of reality, and in the
sentence the fundamental constitution of reality. He overlooked the
fact that thought is only one of the functions of life, and that it is
subservient to life, that it springs out of concrete experience and is
developed primarily out of purely practical interests. Under the
requirements of practical and social life, it produces the elements of
speech and the form of the sentence. In this way the sentence acquires
metaphysical value, and for ordinary thought determines metaphysical
theory. Aristotle unwittingly and uncritically took the grammarian's
point of view, and made the structure of the sentence the basis of his
metaphysics. His logic developed from this starting-point. The
grammatical subject represented the ultimate reality, and the
predicate represented the various states, qualities and activities of
reality. This at once commits us to all the consequences of
intellectualism, and in the end, as we have seen, to materialism.
Subsequent history shows
how these consequences were brought out and adhered to. It is
unnecessary to trace the course of the post-Aristotelian schools, or
to point out that the Stoics and the Epicureans, working with
Aristotelian conceptions, ended in constructing a purely mechanical
universe. The one bright spot in the metaphysics of this period was
that created by the transcendent genius of Plotinus, who for the first
time in the history of philosophy subjected the nature of thought to
systematic and penetrating criticism, and who made out clearly its
instrumental and derivative character. As against Aristotle, he denied
the ultimate reality of thought and affirmed that of feeling.
Unfortunately, he had only Aristotelian terms and concepts to work
with, and these were inadequate for the expression of his insight.
Scholasticism was a
revival of Aristotelianism, and moved strictly within Aristotelian
metaphysics. Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibnitz had the advantage of the
new scientific movement, but they, too, accepted as fundamental the
subject-predicate metaphysics of Aristotle, and endeavored to build
their systems upon it. Descartes made a deliberate attempt to turn his
back on tradition and make a fresh start, but he very soon fell into
the Aristotelian net. The self-assertive, self-certain ego which
Augustine had made fundamental in metaphysics, Descartes cast into the
mould of Aristotle's subject-predicate formula, and proceeded to
develop his system in terms of Aristotelian logic and upon the lines
of familiar tradition. His res cogitans and res extensa
were simple reaffirmations of the old doctrine of substance; and the
two worlds, the spiritual and the material, were merely new editions
of our familiar friends, the sensuous and the super-sensuous realms of
Plato.
Spinoza developed the
doctrine of substance in a more strictly systematic way, and for the
first time brought out the intellectualistic and materialistic
implications of that doctrine.
Leibnitz, with the
possible exception of Plotinus, the greatest metaphysician since
Plato, made some significant alterations in the traditional conception
of substance, and by his doctrine of monads freed it in a measure from
materialistic implications. But even Leibnitz, with all his genius for
analysis and reconstruction, fell a victim to intellectualism. His
monads turn out in the end to be little more than positions in space.
His universe is one in
which nothing ever really happens. The monad, and the universe which
it reflects, are what they are, fixed and eternal. Nothing from the
outside can affect or change the monad, and there is nothing in the
universe which is not already in the monad. In other words, the
ultimately real thing in the universe is the monad and its states, and
these states are eternally self-identical and changeless. Whatever may
be said of this outcome, Leibnitz has the lasting credit of carrying
out (in the realm of ideas) to the logical conclusion the fundamental
conceptions which inhere in any subject-predicate philosophy taken as
an ultimate metaphysic. Every philosophy which makes substance its
fundamental category ends, as first Spinoza and after him Leibnitz
showed, in reducing the universe to states of this substance. The
universe is, then, truly describable by propositions which express
only analytical judgments. The so-called synthetic judgments are
merely premature and provisional forms of thought, which are
convenient for the time being, but which must in the end be set aside
and replaced by the analytic. In other words, all characters,
qualities and properties which are expressed by predicates, inhere in
the subject and are evolved from the subject. These characters, as
such, exist eternally in the subject, and our universe falls back into
a static, self-identical repose. This follows for the reason that both
substance and quality are abstractions and, as such, are colourless,
changeless, self-identical concepts. Such a universe is the product of
abstraction, and was already prefigured in the first attempts of
mankind to use intellectual processes in the service of practical
life, where distinction, separation, analysis and reconstruction are
necessary for success.
We see from this rapid
survey that philosophy chose from the first the intellectualistic
trend, that Aristotle forged its fundamental conceptions, and that
Spinoza and Leibnitz worked these conceptions out to their logical
consequences.
After Leibnitz,
philosophy either went off into psychological and epistemological
excursions, or became severely self-critical. Criticism found its best
expression in the Kantean episode. The constructive efforts of German
idealism may occupy us later, as will also the more recent metaphysics
of the present day.
It is now time to fix
our attention upon a figure and a doctrine which appeared in the
world's intellectual firmament almost without historical associations
or historical introduction. The figure was that of Emanuel Swedenborg,
and the doctrine was his doctrine of love.
In spite of his sudden
and unique appearance upon the world's stage, however, Swedenborg had
some historical relations which must be constantly borne in mind;
otherwise we are liable to misread him. The fact that he wrote in
scholastic Latin puts him in the current of Aristotelian tradition,
since, as we have seen, scholasticism is only Aristotle in mediaeval
Christian dress. In using the language of scholasticism, Swedenborg
naturally adopted the terms and conceptions of Aristotelian
philosophy. This gives his language the superficial appearance of
abstract conceptualism and almost mechanical dogmatism, which has
misled many casual and especially unsympathetic readers. Nevertheless,
we have here the key to his historical position, and it is necessary
to acquire a competent knowledge both of scholasticism and of
Aristotle as a preparation for reading him with critical accuracy.
A more direct relation
to history is indicated by the fact that he was educated at Uppsala
during the period of the Cartesian controversy, and was thus brought
under the spell of the revolutionary spirit, and imbued with the fresh
intellectual impulses of the age. His frequent references to
Aristotle, and his careful study of Wolf, suggest that he was at home
in the earliest and latest phases of traditional philosophy; but there
is little indication that he ever subjected philosophy in whole or in
part to systematic criticism. On the other hand, it seems to have been
his habitual method to take the terms and conceptions as he found
them, embedded in the language and thought of his day, and use them
for his own purpose without caring to keep strictly to their
historical meaning. So that in a general way we may consider
Swedenborg's philosophy as resting, in language at least, rather
loosely upon the basis of scholasticism and common-sense;
understanding by common-sense the popularized results of previous
philosophies. When, therefore, we approach the study of Swedenborg we
must expect to meet the usual mechanical metaphors of ordinary speech
and popular science, as well as the technical terms and conceptions of
a highly refined philosophical vocabulary. At the same time we must be
prepared to see a free use of these as instruments, and be ever
careful to interpret them in the light of his own point of view and
purpose. Our rapid sketch of the history of philosophy has shown us
that the notion of ultimate reality has followed two apparently
diverse tendencies, the one ending in the atomic theory, and the other
in a system of abstract ideas. Around the former have gathered all the
interests of materialism, and around the latter the spiritual ideals
and aspirations of civilized mankind. But the tendencies are really
identical, for the atomic theory is only a convenient stopping-place
in the process of analysis which, when carried out rigorously, ends in
a system of mere positions in space, and this is precisely the outcome
of pushing the analysis of ideas to the extreme. It is really due to
misconception and confusion that idealistic and spiritual interests
have centered about a conceptual world. Such a world is as far as
possible removed from the actual spiritual world. The spiritual world,
like the kingdom of God, is within you. We must therefore turn our
backs on any and every form of conceptual world whatsoever when we
approach Swedenborg for his answer to the question: "What is ultimate
reality?"
Swedenborg's ultimate
reality is in the strictest sense spiritual. His spiritual world was
made known to him in concrete living experience. The divine nature was
revealed to him in the depths of religious feeling and intuition. The
world of nature was to him a mirror of the divine and the human. God
was to him the perfect type of concrete life, equally removed from
Stoic pantheism and the transcendental, abstract wisdom of Aristotle.
Ultimate reality was located by him not in a far-off conceptual
region, but was directly sought in the infinite complexity, variety,
and richness of experience as it comes. Already, in the Principia,
Swedenborg had come to see the futility of attempting to discover
reality by processes of analysis. He saw that logical and mathematical
entities carry you into a field where analysis breaks down, and where
the complexities of life again assert themselves as the real
background. Again, in the work on The Infinite, although the
demands of reason are freely and fully conceded, rational analysis
gives place in the end to the direct affirmation of personal life as
the properly apprehensible reality. Later, in Divine Love and
Wisdom (229), we have the definite and explicit statement that
analysis does not arrive at any simple entity such as the atom or
ultimate particle, but discovers greater and greater complexity.
Indeed, throughout the
period of his illumination Swedenborg consistently assigned to
rationality as its true function the task of taking what was given to
it in spiritual perception, and in this light establishing relations
between the various kinds and degrees of life, especially between
natural and spiritual life. According to him, the substantive element
in life is not thought, but feeling; the element to which we refer
such functions as effort, striving, want, satisfaction, fulfillment,
joy, and the like. Life in its first intention is, for reflection,
that more or less undifferentiated mass of awareness, that sense of
existence, of well-being, of efficiency, of fullness and wholeness
which is the common background, source and fountain of all
particulars, and of all development. Swedenborg sums up the situation
and points us to the central and fundamental feature of experience in
the opening number of Divine Love and Wisdom, by the simple
formula, "Life is love." Swedenborg's doctrine of love is a new
conception in the history of human thought, and philosophically it is
the most important of all the fundamental conceptions which mankind
has framed. All of his other great doctrines grow out of it, and it is
destined to modify fundamentally the philosophy of the world.
In the opening number of
Divine Love and Wisdom, and earlier in Arcana Coelestia,
Swedenborg notes the distinguishing mark which separates experience
into the twofold aspects of immediate, unreflective, massive on the
one hand, and the mediate, reflective, articulate on the other. The
former he designates by the term love, and makes the critical
observation that men have not known what love is, though they have
known of its existence, as the use of the word itself testifies; and
he explains that men have not known what love is because, when they
reflect upon it, they always observe some particular state or
affection of love, some quality distinguished and selected, and so
dissociated from the total mass; or, as we shall say later,
externalized and objectified; but of the love in its immediacy and
wholeness, no idea, mental image or representation can be formed. That
love is life may be argued from the fact that the word can be used
with the names of all the functions of life, as the love of eating, of
music, of children, of nature, of God, and so on indefinitely; and,
further, it is demonstrated by the simple experiment of taking away
all the affections of love, and observing that the activities of life
cease.
Swedenborg further
remarks in criticism of the whole course of philosophy down to his own
day, that for lack of knowing what love is men have made one or the
other of two fundamental mistakes: either maintaining that thought is
life or that action is life. The former is the view of Aristotelianism
and in general of all forms of intellectualism-in short, the view of
the traditional philosophy; the latter of all schools of materialism.
Swedenborg corrects both of these philosophies by affirming that
thought is the first effect of life and action the second effect. He
goes on to make a distinction in the grades of thought, and says that,
strictly speaking, the first effect of life is the thought or
perception of ends. This is inmost thought, or the highest degree of
thought, while thought of means and thought of results, of
accomplished facts, are of relatively lower grade. This passage (No.
2) is important, not only because of its effective criticism of
historic opinion, but because it gives us the key to Swedenborg's
philosophical point of view and method. For there is implied in this
statement his doctrine of end, cause and effect; a doctrine which
gives us the fundamental conceptions of his metaphysics (Divine
Love and Wisdom, 167-72).
We have already seen
that scholasticism was the outcome of the recovery and appropriation
of Greek thought as presented and transmitted in the works of
Aristotle. We have also seen that Aristotle's fundamental conceptions
centered about the notions of subject and predicate, or the notion of
substance. The notion of substance also plays a large part in
Swedenborg's philosophy. Ordinarily, he uses it in the familiar
scholastic context, and when treating it abstractedly helps out his
meaning by the regular scholastic terms, esse, ipsum, unicum, causa
prima, and others. Aristotle, we remember, undertook to interpret
Early Greek philosophy as a search for causes, and he reduced the
conceptions of cause to four. But he finally resolved the notion of
cause into that of substance. Nevertheless, be set out in the
Metaphysics to show that prima philosophia, the highest and
most complete stage of knowledge, is the knowledge of causes. This
idea was transmitted to scholasticism, and reappears variously in
Swedenborg. But both the notion of substance and the notion of cause
were used by him concretely in a way that gave them virtually a new
meaning, and it is in his doctrine of love that he gives them this
concrete meaning.
In the case of substance
this is done most effectively, perhaps, in Divine Love and Wisdom,
Nos. 40-46, where he identifies substance with love. The point of this
teaching is not so much that love is substance as it is that substance
is love. In other words, we are not to identify love with the abstract
conceptual entity ordinarily termed substance, but rather we are to
take the word substance with its whole meaning, and apply it to that
concrete living experience which we know directly, immediately and
intimately as love. This doctrine, so interpreted, constitutes a new
epoch in the history of philosophy, for according to it we turn in our
search for reality from the world of abstract conceptions at once to
the actual, concrete world of living experience, and this experience,
in all its fullness and variety, we now call love. The whole body of
Swedenborg's doctrine, and the philosophy contained in it, is
literally an exposition of the nature of love. In this doctrine love
has many aspects; psychological, moral, religious, theological and
metaphysical. Our present purpose limits us specifically to the
metaphysical. The proper starting-point for the treatment of this
aspect is the development of love in the series of end, cause, and
effect.
We saw that Aristotle,
in treating substance as essence, constructed a theory of development
wherein the two notions of cause, the formal and the final, played the
chief roles. But Aristotle's method led him off into the consequences
of abstract conceptual and mechanical analysis, where all life was in
the end excluded.
Swedenborg adopts the
notion of end, but keeps it concrete and living by conceiving it as a
present state or affection of love. Any such present state, when made
focal to attention and ipso facto objectified, carries with it
the quality and meaning of the love from which it springs, and so is
representative of the love. In other words, the love sees its own
quality and meaning reflected, revealed and existent in the state as
in a specific instance or form. When the state or affection, with its
quality and meaning, is taken as thus representative, the meaning
suggests fulfillment, and this becomes an object of desire, striving,
and anticipated satisfaction. The formation and existence of such
states are characteristic of life. The process involves all those
functions which correspond to the words awareness, consciousness,
feeling, emotion, effort, striving, longing, change, activity, force,
movement, and a host of others, which are all summed up in the word
love. All these qualities lie behind the state and seek expression in
it; and it belongs to the intimate and constant nature of love to
project and constitute such states. It is its creative function, a
function of self-propulsion, generation, limitation, definition. To
use a gross figure of speech, though one consecrated by Plotinus, love
is the total mass of feeling or awareness which bubbles up and bubbles
over in those forms of experience we call particular states or
affections. To use a figure less materialistic, love is the body of
spirit which possesses all the qualities it reveals, and these, as
they emerge in distinct consciousness and are observed and identified
as persistent or frequent, and defined as uniform, receive names, and
so become fixed, established and communicable features of experience.
Such qualities come to view out of the depths of love unceasingly and
with endless variety. Being present, living, self-conscious,
self-identical affections of love, they are its self-representative
images, in which the love sees its own longing for self-realization
reproduced in the definite striving of the particular affection. In
this relation, the affection presents to the love the opportunity for
further fulfillment; and as offering such fulfillment the affection is
an end. The character of fulfillment is fundamental in the processes
of life. Around it cluster innumerable functions which are, as it
were, polarized with respect to it. The elements of desire, longing,
striving, effort, and such-like, are distinguished from those of
satisfaction, contentment, enjoyment, realization, fulfillment,
achievement, and so on. The latter are set over against and contrasted
with the former. In this way the characters of nearness and remoteness
arise as contrasting features of experience. With nearness goes the
feeling of intimacy and immediacy; and these, as properties of the
former group, are referred to the basic, undifferentiated total
background which, in the language of our present discourse, we call
the active, generating, particularizing love. This reference is made
by such words as "I," "me," "subject," "subjective." On the other
hand, the group of characters clustering about the element of
fulfillment are more and more dissociated from the primary mass and
consolidated into an independent group. The process here involved we
denote variously by such words as "project," "externalize,"
"objectify"; while of the group thus distinguished and set off we use,
among others, the words "objective" and "object." Meanwhile, all that
we are really doing is simply observing the affections of love and
making distinctions in its activities and functions. One of these
functions, inhering in the essence of love and coextensive with its
being, is the function variously termed seeing, perception, awareness,
consciousness, thought, wisdom, and so on almost indefinitely. Love is
throughout and always pervaded by and possessed of this function in
the whole and in every detail. It is that function whereby two states
of love are mutually present to each other, and share each other's
qualities, but at the same time preserve each their own self-identity
and also their difference from each other. It is by virtue of this
function of knowing that the mysterious parting of experience into
subjective and objective aspects takes place. The act of knowing is
simple and original; it cannot be reduced to lower terms; but the very
act itself generates those characters of contrast, otherness and
remoteness which we denote by the words objectivity and object.
With this conception of
love let us return to the consideration of ends. An affection,
projected and constituted an end with the characters of remoteness,
self-identity and independence, is a perceptive mass having perceptive
relations with the total love of which it is a present, living,
particular state. The total love sees in the end the fulfillment of
its own purpose, and the end sees in the love the conditions of its
own fulfillment. The total love strives to fill the end with its own
immediate presence, satisfaction and enjoyment; the end strives to
gather into itself all the insights, satisfactions, enjoyments, and
activities of the love. This situation is exemplified in the
biological field by the behaviour of a simple cell, which is ever
putting forth parts of its mass in the form of projections. Among the
many various projections it selects one, and then gradually moves its
whole mass into this terminus or end. This is the type of all movement
in the organic world. The earthworm extends its forward extremity and
then draws the rest of its body toward it, and in this way moves from
place to place. More highly organized animals put forward certain
parts called limbs, and then draw the body into the new position. In
this way bodily movement is effected. But mental movement is precisely
similar in type. The mind, spirit, love, projects a part of its mass
in what we call an end. Then it moves into that end, and thus makes
the end a new centre. This we call making progress, moving to a new
position, or fulfilling a purpose. In the case of man, and presumably
the higher animals, this mental motion is so co-ordinated with the
bodily functions that it gives rise to bodily motion. In other words,
the mind carries the body with it in the fulfillment of purposes. The
behaviour of a simple cell is thus seen to be typical of the nature
and movement of universal life, that is, of universal love. The word
end is properly used for the terminus of this movement. In
Swedenborg's language (Divine Love and Wisdom, 167) it is
called an end because it is the end of this movement of the state of
love.
We now pass to the
second stage of the end. As a state to be reached, the end is an idea.
It is, as we have seen, a particularized affection of love which has
emerged and become disengaged from the immediacy of feeling by the act
of attention, and thus set off from the love. This whole process is
summed up in the word objectify. Any state is objectified, made an
object, by the mere fact of fixing attention upon it. It is thereby
distinguished and selected from among the numberless constantly
emerging states which occupy the conscious threshold. An idea, then,
is a state of consciousness which is of the essence of love in that as
a self-projection of the love it retains the qualities of the love; in
general, the qualities of feeling and perception. The love is
therefore self-represented in the idea. But an idea tends to develop
relations to other states of love, whether these be other ideas or
mere vague feelings, or more pronounced states, such as emotions,
longings, desires. Between the idea and all such states there is
mutual reference and participation by virtue of their common ground in
the love and their relation to the love as its self-representatives.
The mutual relations between the idea and the love as exhibited in the
totality of such mediating states constitute the field of articulate
consciousness, or, to use the specific term, the field of love's
wisdom. In fact, it is perhaps the most fundamental definition of
wisdom to say that it is love's self-representative function; for the
field of this function is the system of ideas projected as perceptive
units from the total love. When in this field one of these perceptive
units is selected as, for the moment, or the occasion, the special
embodiment of the meaning and purpose of love, this unit then becomes
the vehicle of love's fulfillment, and as such is what we have called
an end. But; evidently, in the passage to fulfillment, between the
stage of want, desire, longing, striving, and that of satisfaction and
achievement, there intervenes the field of ideas through which the
love and the end co-operate in bringing about the fulfillment. The end
selects within the field of ideas those which are referred to in its
meaning and which seek embodiment in itself. The love with reference
to the end chooses the same ideas as being contained within its
purpose. At this stage the end exists as a system of ideas contained
within a single purpose, and organized about the initial state whose
meaning develops into this system. But this second stage of the end,
or second end, is constituted of ideas which have the common feature
of pointing to a situation in which the organization is complete, the
meanings expressed, the desires fulfilled and purpose achieved. The
affection originally projected and constituted an end is now no longer
felt merely as a state to be realized, but the conditions of
realization are actually present, and the affection is concretely
existent and active in its sought-for context and environment. The
end, therefore, exists successively in three stages: (1) As present
affection whose meaning points to a situation to be constructed by the
group of ideas and affections in which the meaning would be fulfilled;
(2) As the system of ideas included within the meaning of the
affection and pointing to the situation in which that meaning would be
fulfilled; (3) As the completely organized group wherein the affection
and its system of ideas are concretely existent and active. In this
concrete, active existence we have the fact of fulfillment.
If, now, we review this
process, it is evident that the second stage arises, as a development
of the first, in a context of elements which first come into the new
relation by being selected as included within the meaning of the end;
in other words, the end is self-represented in them. But these states
in which the end at this stage exists are themselves developed out of
the concrete mass of the total love as its self-representatives. They
therefore carry with them the qualities of the love seeking
fulfillment in the end. This relation to fulfillment we call, in
common speech, “means." Further, it is evident that it is the
collection and grouping of these subsidiary ends with reference to
fulfillment that produces the concrete situation which is had in view
from the beginning. This third stage, then, is brought into existence
by completing the process of fitting together the relatively
dissociated and independent elements of the second stage into the
organized context of the initial affection. The result is properly
termed a product, and the efficiency of the process that leads to the
result is expressed by the word cause. In ordinary language the
relation between these stages, the second and third, is expressed by
the terms cause and effect. The three stages may be designated
respectively affection, idea, fact. Affection is the present,
immediate element of feeling; idea, the more or less dissociated
elements to be grouped; fact, the concrete existence of the affection
in its new context, the completely organized group.
This is Swedenborg's
doctrine of end, cause, and effect; and it is a doctrine which grows
directly out of his conception of love. With this conception in mind,
we see the full significance of such statements as: "There are three
things that follow in order, called first end, middle end, and last
end; they are also called end, cause, and effect. These three must be
in everything that it may be anything" (Divine Love and Wisdom,
167). Again (168), "The end is everything in the cause and everything
in the effect."
As these three stages of
love grow out of its inmost and complete nature, they must belong to
it universally.
The processes of
self-projection, self-representation, and self-realization which we
have found to be the essential characteristics of experience as we
directly and most intimately know it in our own personal life, we
assume to be characteristic of all experience. If we look at the
universe in the light of this view, we see that it is in the strictest
sense the process of love. The processes of self-projection,
self-representation and self-realization are everywhere going on.
Assuming the truth of the nebular hypothesis, the planets of our solar
system are in origin, projected masses of the sun, and in the planets
the activities of the sun are reproduced and continued. The earth is
everywhere putting up from its mass the bodies of plants. Plants are
forever reproducing themselves in the form of seeds. Likewise animals.
In the mental or spiritual world we see the perpetual processes of
putting forth ideas and realizing ideals or ends. Production,
reproduction, action, creation, life, are just names for the processes
of love. In short, the universe is love. This being the case, the
background of the universe, its core, what we otherwise call its
source, first cause, or prime substance, is the total love in its
aspect and capacity of forming ends of numberless grades of
comprehensiveness. The most comprehensive would be the
self-represented idea of the universe itself, in which the full nature
and whole purpose of the love would be expressed. The variety, order
and subordination of ends point to that character of love which can be
adequately expressed only in an infinite system, a system in which
self-propagation is the law. From this point of view love exhibits the
character of an infinity of infinities. Among such infinities are the
animal and plant series ; also such series as the rational and moral
life. It is as a member of such series, and as constituting such
series, that the individual is a proper function of the universe, and
is related to the universe as a whole.
Among the more
comprehensive grades of ends, we distinguish the relatively free and
the relatively fixed. Self-projected states of love may preserve,
according to their meaning and purpose, a separateness and
independence which allows only a relatively free context, which is
developed largely from its own self-active nature. We call this realm
in general the spiritual world. In our personal finite life we have
something analogous in what we call the ideal world. In either case
the characteristic is self-developing freedom. The total life of the
spiritual world is the expression of one purpose: the purpose, namely,
to represent and realize particular states of love under relatively
free conditions.
But the end thus
constituted is pervaded with meanings which point to further
fulfillment. The self-representative and self-realizing nature of love
demands greater remoteness, otherness, independence, and
self-sufficiency on the part of its self-projected states. Such states
are self-representative in the measure of their relatively independent
self-activity. This purpose of love is fulfilled in those
self-identical centres which are organized in relatively stable
groups. In this way a further comprehensive end is constituted, which
has in view a compact organization of such centres and groups. This
region we call the natural world. The natural world, then, is a second
comprehensive end, differing from the end we have called the spiritual
world by the fact that it is fulfilled under conditions of greater
fixity, uniformity and self-identity. Thus we have three grades of
ends, or three degrees of existence; the divine, the spiritual, and
the natural.
The divine is
self-represented in the spiritual and, through the spiritual, in the
natural. This is the relation of correspondence. It is self-realized
in the spiritual and, through the spiritual, in the natural. This is
influx. The spiritual and the natural are self-projections of the
divine. This is creation.
It would take volumes to
work out in detail the various aspects of this doctrine of love, but
we all remember that remarkable section in Divine Love and Wisdom
headed, "There are three things in the Lord which are the Lord: the
Divine of Love, the Divine of Wisdom, and the Divine of Use. These
three are correlated with the three degrees of ends or end, cause, and
effect."
We have in this
statement doctrine about the constitution of the personal life
universally, and it is doctrine about the constitution of ultimate
reality. According to it, ultimate reality is personal life, and
personal life is love.
The latest phase of
modern philosophy tends to this conclusion, and the best efforts of
modern philosophy, notably those of Mr. Bradley here in Oxford, and
Professor Royce over the sea in Harvard, may be read as partial
expositions of Swedenborg's doctrine of love.
Speaking, then, in the
light of history and of doctrine, we may affirm that Ultimate Reality
is Love. |